2. The Person as a Psychosomatic Unity
Another approach is
to start with the Biblical concept of the human person as an psychosomatic
unity and
explore our understanding of this concept fully in light of evolutionary
biology. Jürgen Moltmann begins his theological anthropology by asking, not
with what distinguishes humanity from other animals, but with what links humans
with all other creatures through the evolution of life. The imago dei is
first of all the imago mundi Humanity is a microcosm in which all other
creatures are found in community, speaking and acting on their behalf before
God. Humanity is formed from, bound to, and returns to, adama, the
earth (Gen. 2.7), being an animated body not, with Plato, a soul enfleshed.
Yet humanity is also Gods proxy in creation, interceding for God before the
community of creation. Neither submerged into creation nor detached from it,
humanity stands before the sabbath to prepare the feast of creation.For Rosemary Radford Ruether, the earth forms a living system, Gaia, of which
humans are an inextricable part. In the West we have construed our view of
humans as over against all that is nonhuman, and we call all that is both
nonhuman and non-divine, nature. Yet nature in Ruethers sense includes
humans and their constant modification of the ecosystems of the world.
But taking a psychosomatic approach to the human person also
exposes theology to sociobiology, behavioral genetics, and the cognitive and
neurosciences, and their reductionist interpretations. Will a psychosomatic
portrayal of the human person survive these challenges? And will theologians be
able to rid themselves of what Fergus Kerr points to as a lingering
philosophical Cartesianismwhose adherance is declaimed by Antonio Damasio in Descartes Error?Admittedly, many of these scientific areas are routinely layered with
deterministic and reductionistic interpretations, often by the scientists
themselves, although some allowance is occasionally made for the emergence of
new sociological and psychological processes and properties.Moreover, it is surely the intent theologically to find a middle ground
between even an implicit Cartesian dualism and eliminative materialism. Hence,
I will focus on constructive, non-reductive theological responses in light of
these results.
According to Peacocke, Christian anthropology assumes the
psychosomoatic unity of the person rooted in materialitywhile the sciences shed increasing light on the multileveled character and
evolutionary history of this unity. His description of the hierarchy of
disciplines is particularly
helpful in showing the impact of the physical, biological, neuro, cognitive,
and behaviourial sciences on the meaning of homo sapiens. In a 1999
essay, he further developed an emergentist-monist account of the personal as
an emergent level above the purely biological, and he attributed mental
preperties to the human-brain-in-the-body-in-social-relations.He defended the causal irreducibility of mental states as well, describing the
relation between person and brain in terms of downward causation and whole-part
influence. His panentheistic view of Gods relation to the world-as-a-whole
then makes possible an analogous view of divine action and special revelation
as mediated through the human and natural worlds.
In his many writings on theological anthropology, Peacocke
is always careful to stress what we should learn from sociobiology, though he
is sharply critical of its incipient reductionism.The issues cannot be treated in terms of a simple nature/nurture dichotomy;
instead we must recognize both the multileveled character of humanity and the
fact that all human behavior, no matter how complex, is rooted in our
evolutionary biology. Lindon Eaves and colleagues, for example, provide strong
evidence relating variations in human personal attitude and social behavior
with genetic predispositions, though they are careful to disavow full-scale
genetic determinism.At the same time, human behavior plays a dual role in our evolution. As Gunter
Altner stresses, it is both a product of evolution and a system of feedback
which, at least in homo sapiens, actually shapes human evolution by
shaping our environment.
Still the reductionist challenge is most severe when
considering moral reasoning. According to Michael Ruse and others, moral
altruism in humans has neither an objective reference nor can it be justified
rationally. Instead, it is a biological adaptation rooted in our genes to help
our species compete.But Peacocke charges Ruse with falling into the genetic fallacy: origins
determine outcome. Instead he claims that the content of moral reasoning cannot
be determined by, even if it is shaped by, its evolutionary history and
biological basis, and that human creativity requires a language other than that
of biology. Theologically we should view the human experience of free will and
moral agency within the matrix of a multi-leveled, genetically based
psychosomatic unity, as part of Gods purposes in continuously creating through
the processes of evolution.
In treating the problem of sin, most scholars in theology
and science reject traditional notions of the Fall and any connection between
sin and biological death. Peacocke,for example, discusses sin in terms of our unique sense, differing from all
other species, of being radically alienated from our own nature and from
non-human nature: humanity ... is a kind of misfit in its biological
environment. He finds
contemporary theological formulations of sin closely attuned to an evolutionary
understanding of human nature. These include sin as falling short, as
failure to realize potentiality, and as being in tension between
self-centeredness and openness, and as unfulfilled paradox, all of which
issue from our being created as free to respond, or not, to God.
Two of the most notable features of Philip Hefners
theological anthropology are his sustained critical interaction with
sociobiology and the way he has recently structured his work explicitly in
terms of a Lakatosian research program.His work is deeply informed by the work of Ralph Wendell Burhoeand Solomon Katz,as well as by his commitment to Lutheran theology and a Trinitarian doctrine of
God, and by his profound appreciation for Teilhard de Chardin.The core of Hefners proposal is to interpret the imago dei as created
co-creator: Human beings are Gods created co-creators whose purpose is to be
the agency, acting in freedom, to birth the future that is most wholesome for
the nature that has birthed us. Homo sapiens is thus a two-natured
creature, a symbiosis of genes and culture. Though genetics makes culture as an
evolutionary emergent possible, genes and culture have co-evolved; as Burhoe
put it, they constitute two organisms that are co-adapted, distinguishing
humanity from other speciesHefner thus rejects both anthropocentric and biocentric views of humanity
through his claim that human meaning and purpose must be related to that of
nature as a whole while not being reduced to it. Nature is crucial since nature
is the medium of both divine knowledge and grace. Culture is crucial since
myth, ritual and religion are critical sources of information and guidance for
the future of life on earth. Such guidance is urgently needed since
technological civilization massively affects the planet. Still technology is
neither alien to nature nor should it be subordinated to nature; instead
technology is fully part of evolution, rooted in the genes/culture
symbiosis... Hefner,
obviously, rejects the Fall except in a figurative sense, but he takes very seriously
original sin, freedom and sacrifice, drawing on insights from Schleiermacher,
both Western and Eastern Christianity, Tillich and feminist theology and
demonstrating the commensurability of both theological and biological insights
on sin and evil.Remarkably, Hefner lists a number of potential falsifiers of his proposal, such
as dualistic views of technology and human nature, or reductionist arguments
about religion as merely functional or culture as reducible to genetics.He predicts that a biocultural perspective will prove more fruitful than either
instrumental or intrinsic / biocentric values, that the human sciences will
come to view myth, ritual and religion as essential to human nature, and that
nature itself shares in the imago dei of the created co-creator.
Finally we should note very recent criticisms of
reductionism in sociobiology by Holmes Rolston and by Nancey Murphy. In his
1999 Gifford Lectures,
Holmes Rolston pursues a theme he has long championed: that values are inherent
in nature but morals only arise with human culture. Values in nature include
intrinsic values (e.g., the lives of individuals), instrumental values (e.g.,
parenting or food chains), and systemic values (e.g., interactive ecological
systems). These values must be generated initially, and then regenerated and
distributed indefinitely, and genes provide the means.Genetic information thus tells the organism how to survive, but it is
inappropriate to label this knowledge selfish as sociobiologists and
behavioral ecologists do. Worse yet, this mistaken view of nature is
reintroduced into culture with the claim that all human behavior (is) pervaded
with genetic self-interest, a self-interest which is seen as determining all
human relations. (A)ll this can lead to a misvaluing of what is legitimately
to be appreciated in both nature and culture...and how values (in each domain)
are transmitted and shared.Reminiscent of his earlier claim that values are tertiary properties in
nature, Rolston
sees Earth as a value-generating system, value-genic, valuable, value-able,
that is, able to generate values that are widely distributed... over the face
of the Earth. Granted that only humans evaluate, and to do so we must set up
scales. But (t)he axiological scales we construct do not constitute the value,
any more than the scientific scales we erect create what we thereby measure.
In 1998, Murphycontinued her philosophical argument against reductionism in the sphere of
biology and morality, picking up themes from her previous writings.She draws on the work of Roy Wood Sellars, R. M. Hare, and Donald Davidson in
deploying nonreductive physicalism with a focus on both emergent properties in
hierarchical systems and on supervenience. Here identical behavior in different
circumstances could constitute different moral judgments, and such
supervenient properties are not necessarily reducible. In her epistemic
model, developed with Ellis, the human sciences are incomplete without ethics,
and thus the moral supervenes on the biological. After drawing on Alasdair
MacIntyre and Philip Kitcher to critique E. O. Wilsons reductionism, she
places ethics between the social sciences and theology. Since the social
sciences are not value-free but involve moral presuppositions and ethical
questions, the role of theology in providing them is thus of crucial
importance.
The neurosciences pose a particularly challenging set of
issues to theology. Claytondismisses both substance dualism and eliminative reductive materialism as theologically
unacceptable, but this still leaves a variety of theological options which are
neither contradicted by the sciences nor reducible to them. His own approach is
to view mental events as supervenient on their neural states such that there is
room for geniune mental causation of somatic disposition. His
emergentist-monist account of the person is then open to rich theological
interpretation. In a recent joint paper, Wesley Wildman and Leslie Brothershave also focused on the reductionist challenge posed by the neurosciences to
the claims of ultimacy as a causal source of religious experience. They first
present a richly textured interpretation of the experiences of ultimacy as
objectively as possible in hopes that authetic religious experiences can be
distinguished from mere claims to them. They then attempt to evaluate the
claims made to explain their cause, drawing on semiotics. Addressing the nature
and possibility of religious experience in light of the cognitive
neurosciences, Fraser Wattshas argued that theological and neurological explanations of such experience
are complementary, not contradictory. Eugene dAquilis theory of cognitive
operators provides a helpful starting point, but Watts own thesis is that a
truly adequate cognitive theory of religious experience should draw on
analogies between religious and emotional experience. Most helpful here are
multileveled theories which distinguish between sensory-motor aspects and the
interpretation of religious experience, with attention to intuitive perceptions
of meaning and the propositional descriptions of experience.
Contributed by: Dr. Robert Russell
|