Barbour, Ian G. Five Models of God and Evolution.
In the first part of his paper,
Ian Barbour describes the evolution of Darwinism over the past century. Charles
Darwin actually shared many of the mechanistic assumptions of Newtonian
science. By the early twentieth century, population genetics focused on
statistical changes in the gene pool and the modern synthesis took a
gradualist view of evolution. The discovery of the structure of DNA in 1953 led
to the central dogma of molecular biology: information flows from DNA to
protein. Recent theories have explored selection at a variety of levels
including gene, organism, kin, group, and species, as well as punctuated
equilibrium. Other biologists have noted that mutation and selection are not
the only sources of novelty. While these new theories can be seen as extensions
of Darwinism, a few scientists, such as Stuart Kaufman, claim they are moving
beyond Darwinism by invoking principles of self-organization and holism.
Barbour then outlines four
philosophical issues which characterize the interpretation of evolution. Self-organization is the expression of
built-in potentialities and constraints in complex hierarchically-organized
systems. This may help to account for the directionality of evolutionary
history without denying the role of law and chance. Indeterminacy is a pervasive characteristic of the
biological world. Unpredictability sometimes only reflects human ignorance, but
in the interpretation of quantum theory, indeterminacy is a feature of the
microscopic world and its effects can be amplified by non-linear biological
systems. He also argues for top-down
causality in which higher-level events impose boundary conditions on
lower levels without violating lower- level laws and he places top-down
causality within the broader framework of holism. He distinguishes between
methodological, epistemological, and ontological reduction. Communication of information is another
important concept in many fields of science, from the functioning of DNA to
metabolic and immune systems and human language. In each case, a message is
effective only in a context of interpretation and response.
According
to Barbour, each of these has been used as a non-interventionist model of Gods
relation to the world in recent writings. If God is the designer of a self-organizing process as Paul Davies
suggests, it would imply that God respects the worlds integrity and human
freedom. Theodicy is a more tractable problem if suffering and death are
inescapable features of an evolutionary process for which God is not directly
responsible. But do we end up with the absentee God of deism? The neo-Thomist view of God as primary cause working through secondary
causes as defended by Bill Stoeger tries to escape this conclusion, but Barbour
thinks it undermines human freedom. Alternatively, God as providential determiner of indeterminacies could
actualize one of the potentialities present in a quantum probability
distribution. Selection of one of the co-existing potentialities would
communicate information without energy input, since the energy of the
alternative outcomes is identical. Does God then control all quantum indetermi
nacies - or only some of them? Barbour comments on the way these options have
been discussed by George Ellis, Nancey Murphy, Robert Russell, and Thomas
Tracy. God as top-down cause
might represent divine action on the world as a whole, as Arthur Peacocke
maintains together with his whole-part models. But these are problematic
according to Barbour since the universe does not have a spatial boundary, and
the concept of the-world-as-a-whole is inconsistent with relativity theory.
Grace Jentzen and Sallie McFague view the world as Gods body but Barbour is
concerned that this model breaks down when applied to the cosmos. God as communicator of information would act
through the pattern of events in the world, in human thought, and in Christs
life as Gods self-expression, but this model does not capture Gods intention
in creating loving and responsible people.
Process theology offers a
fifth model of Gods action in the world by providing a distinctive theme: the interiority of all integrated events
viewed as moments of experience. Rudimentary forms of perception, memory, and
response are present in lower organisms; sentience, purposiveness, and
anticipation are found in vertebrates. But process authors maintain that
consciousness occurs only at the highest levels of complex organisms. There is
great diversity in the ways in which components are organized in complex
systems, and therefore great differences in the types of experience that can occur.
The process model resembles
but differs from each of the four models above. God as designer of
self-organizing systems is a source of order, but the God of process thought is
also a source of novelty. God acts in indeterminacies at the quantum level, but
also within integrated entities at higher levels. God acts as top-down cause,
not through the cosmic whole but within each integrated system which is part of
a hierarchy of interconnected levels. Communication of information can occur
through events at any level, not primarily through quantum events at the bottom
or the cosmic whole at the top. God is persuasive, with power intermediate
between the omnipotent God of classical theism and the absentee God of deism.
God is present in the unfolding of every event, but God never exclusively
determines the outcome. This is consistent with the theme of Gods
self-limitation in contemporary theology and with the feminist advocacy of
power as empowerment. Process theology has much in common with the biblical understanding
of the Holy Spirit as Gods activity in the world. Barbour concludes by
considering some objections to process thought concerning panexperientialism,
Gods power, the charge of being a gaps approach, and the abstract character
of philosophical categories in the context of theology.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback | Contributed by: CTNS/Vatican Observatory
|