Two Senses in Which the Universe Is Designed
The idea of divine design is
not one that process theologians naturally use, because it suggests that the
creation of our universe came about in accordance with a detailed blueprint,
prepared in advance. But if we
understand the term design in a looser sense, to mean that the universe
reflects some sort of purpose, then process theologians can speak of the
universe as designed in two senses.
First, the evolutionary process is viewed as reflecting a divine aim at
increasing richness of experience, a directionality that is reflected in the
rise of life and then the more complex forms of life. Second, the fact that our universe was able to bring forth life
presupposed a basic cosmological order that can, with less qualification, be
described as designed. I will discuss
these two types of design in order.
Design in the
Sense of a Divine Aim Towards Richness of Experience
Physicists, we are told, think
of the universe as a physics experiment.
Whitehead came to regard it as an aesthetic experiment, with the physics
experiment being simply an aspect of this larger project. To explain:
Experience is the only thing that is intrinsically valuable, meaning
valuable in and for itself. Every
individual, by hypothesis, has at least some slight degree of experience and
thereby some slight degree of intrinsic value.
But the intrinsic value of the simplest individuals, judged in terms of
the aesthetic criteria of harmony, complexity, and intensity of experience,
must be extremely trivial, compared with the intrinsic value of a human being,
or even a bat. If, as Thomas Nagel has emphasized, we cannot imagine what it is
like to be a bat,far less can we imagine what it is like to be at atom, or even an amoeba. The divine aim, by hypothesis, has been to
bring about conditions that allow for the emergence of individuals with more
complex modes of experience and thereby the capacity for greater intrinsic
value. This aim is reflected in the
increasing complexity that, even allowing for all necessary qualifications,
clearly characterizes the evolutionary process.
The slowness of this process
reflects the fact that the power behind this aim is not omnipotent in the
traditional sense, not essentially the only center of power. Each event, having its own power of
self-determination, can either adopt or resist divinely proffered novel
possibilities through which the present situation could be transcended. And this present situation is supported by
the power of the past, which weighs heavily on the present. Charles Peirce and William James had
suggested that the so-called laws of nature are really its most long-standing
habits,which would mean that any type of enduring individual, such as a proton, a DNA
molecule, or a living cell, would be a more or less long-standing habit. Peirce held that the longer a habit
persists, the stronger it tends to become.
This idea led him to the conclusion that the universe would become
increasingly deterministic, as the habits of nature became stronger and
stronger, thereby imposing themselves more and more heavily on the
present. Whitehead, while endorsing the
idea that the laws of nature are habits, avoided the idea of increasing determinism
partly by means of his doctrine of the divine reality as constantly presenting
alternative possibilities. This divine
influence, however, cannot unilaterally determine either what new possibility,
if any, will be evoked or when this development will occur, because the divine
evocative power is always competing with the power of the past embodied in the
habits of enduring individuals. It may
take, accordingly, hundreds, thousands, or even millions of years for an
alternative possibility to be evoked into existence.
Although this hypothesis is
consistent with both the tempo and the direction of the evolutionary process,
it might be thought that it goes against a scientifically established randomness
in the process. But the idea that all
variations are random has more than one meaning. I have already endorsed one possible meaning, which is that
variations involve chance in the ontological sense, an idea that Darwin himself
and some neo-Darwinists have rejected.
A meaning that many neo-Darwinists do insist upon is that variations are
random in every other possible sense, which would exclude their being due even
in the slightest to any sort of aim that would give a bias toward variations of
a particular sort, such as variations that lead to greater structural
complexity and thereby greater richness of experience. But the neo-Darwinian insistence that
evolution is random in this sense is simply philosophical dogma, not grounded
in any empirical discovery. The
randomness that is central to neo-Darwinism as a scientific theory is
randomness in a third sense,according to which there is no tendency for variations to be adaptational, that
is, advantageous for survival in the environment in which they occur. And the kind of tendency that process
theology posits is not in conflict with randomness in this strict sense,
because there is no necessary correlation between increased richness of
experience and success in the struggle for survival. To give a human example:
The emergence of the capacity to do higher mathematics, while it may
have increased the satisfaction of some early human beings on the savannas of
Africa, would not have increased the likelihood of their sowing their wild
genes. The criterion of greater
richness of experience is not in tension with neo-Darwinian randomness, except
insofar as this randomness is used as a pseudo-scientific front for
antitheistic bias.
The divine aim towards greater
richness of experience means that there is, in spite of what I said earlier
about the contingency of human beings, a sense in which we can regard ourselves
as intended. That is, insofar as human
experience involves dimensions that give it the capacity for greater intrinsic
value than that enjoyed by our evolutionary predecessors, we can say that we
reflect the divine aim. Although human
beings as such were not intended, human-like beings were, insofar as they were
possible. This would mean that, on
other planets in the universe with the conditions for life to emerge and to
evolve for many billions of years, we should expect there to be some planets
with creatures that, no matter how different in physical constitution and
appearance, would share some of our capacities, such as those for mathematics,
music, and morality, or, more generally, truth, beauty, and goodness.
These capacities, however,
imply the capacities for lying, for ugliness, and for immorality, such as
genocide and ecological destruction.
Must we not conclude, therefore, that the divine individual of process
theology is as responsible for evil as was the deity of traditional
theism? It is true that process
theologys deity is responsible for evil in one sense, namely, that if human
beings had not been evoked into existence, the world would have been free from
all the evils caused and experienced by human beings. The question of theodicy, however, is whether the divine reality
is responsible in such a way as to be indictable, that is, blameworthy.
With regard to this question, process
theism differs from traditional theism in two crucial respects. In the first place, given the omnipotence
attributed to the deity of traditional theism, that deity could have created
beings who were identical to us in virtually all respects, having the capacity
for realizing most of the values we enjoy, differing only by having much less,
or even no, power to bring about evil.
Because this traditional deity created our world ex nihilo, all the principles of our world were freely chosen. There were no metaphysical principles lying
in the nature of things, beyond divine volition. In process theology, by contrast, such principles do exist, and
one of these principles is that an increase in the capacity for richness of
experience is impossible without a correlative increase in freedom and the
power to affect other beings. This
principle means that every increase in the capacity for good entails an equal
increase in the capacity for evil. Any
being with our capacities to experience and create good, therefore, would
necessarily have our capacities to experience and cause evil. Insofar as we think of the divine individual
as confronting a choice with regard to the existence of human-like beings, the
choice was only between having beings approximately like us, with our
capacities for evil as well as for good, or no human-like beings
whatsoever. The deity of process
theology can be indicted because of human evil, therefore, only by those who
can honestly say that our planet would have been better without human-like
beings altogether.
A second crucial difference
between the two types of theism is that, according to traditional theism, every
instance of evil that has occurred could have been unilaterally prevented by
God. One version of traditional theism,
to be sure, says that God gave us genuine freedom, so that we can freely choose
to do evil. It remains the case,
however, that the deity of traditional theism could always intervene either to
determine our decisions or to cancel out the natural effects thereof--hence the
anger of virulent antitheists such as Steven Weinberg. In process theism, by contrast, the divine
power cannot do either of these.
Although the human degree of freedom would not exist if the divine power
had not led the evolutionary process to bring human beings into existence, now
that we do exist the divine power cannot cancel out our power to make our own
decisions and to inflict them on others.
The sense of meaning that comes from seeing the evolutionary process as
divinely influenced is not, therefore, undermined or rendered horrible by the
conclusion that the divine influence is actually demonic, or at least
indifferent.
Design
in the Sense of the Establishment of the Most Fundamental Contingent Principles
of Our Cosmic Epoch I will conclude by briefly explaining the second sense in
which process theology can regard our universe as designed. This second sense involves the
much-discussed idea that our universe from the outset evidently embodied a
number of cosmic constants that give the impression of being finely tuned in
relation to each other, because if any of them were slightly different, life
could never have evolved. And they do
not seem to be simply habits, as usually understood--that is, to be modes of
behavior that have developed gradually and are only usually, rather than
always, followed. Some traditional
theists have used this fact as new evidence that our universe is the product of
Omnipotent Intelligence. Such theists
might argue that, even if process theism, with its non-omnipotent deity, can do
justice to the worlds evil, it cannot do justice to the best scientific
account of how our universe originated.
A divine being whose power can be resisted by the creatures could not,
they might argue, have imposed all of these mathematical values with sufficient
precision to pull off an initial creative event, such as a big bang, that would
bring about all the conditions necessary for life to be possible in portions of
the resulting universe. Although that conclusion might at first glance seem to
follow from what I said earlier, I argue that it does not.
My argument is that, in a
chaotic state prior to the beginning of our cosmic epoch, the two reasons why
there is usually so much resistance to divine ideals would not apply. One of these reasons is that, as the
evolutionary process increasingly brings forth more complex individuals, the
world thereby has creatures with increasingly greater capacity for
self-determination and thereby increasingly greater capacity to resist divine
influence. In a chaotic state between
cosmic epochs, however, the events would be extremely trivial, with a
vanishingly small capacity to exercise self-determination.
The second reason why divine
influence usually encounters so much resistance is that the divine intention to
instill new ideals, meaning new possible modes of being and interacting, is
usually in competition with the power of the past, the modes of being that
constitute the essence of enduring individuals. However, in the postulated chaos between the running down of one
cosmic epoch and the starting up of another, there would, by definition, be no
enduring individuals, therefore no entrenched modes of being to force
themselves upon present events. The
chaos would not be absolute, to be sure, because events would still exemplify
the necessary metaphysical principles, which by definition obtain in all
possible worlds, including the relatively chaotic periods between cosmic
epochs. But there would be no
contingent cosmological principles constituting well-entrenched habits. In this situation, therefore, the divine influence, in seeking to get a
set of contingent principles embodied in the universe, would have no
competition from any other contingent principles.
In the first instant of the
creation of a particular universe, accordingly, divine evocative power could
produce quasi-coercive effects. A
divine spirit, brooding over the chaos, would only have to think Let there be
X!--with X standing for the finely-tuned set of contingent principles embodied
in our world at the outset. To say this
is not to suggest that this effect would necessarily have occurred
immediately. It is also not to deny the
possibility that our universe might have been preceded by a number of brief universes,
which were not sufficiently fine-tuned to last very long. But it is to suggest an alternative to the
three major ways of thinking of the laws of physics of our universe: that they are necessary, that they exist
purely by chance, or that they are the product of an Omnipotent Designer. This alternative possibility is that a
creator without coercive power could, in a chaotic situation, produce
quasi-coercive effects. From then on,
however, the divine persuasive activity would always face competition from the
power embodied in the modes of being reflecting these contingent principles, so
that divine power would never again, as long as the cosmic epoch exists, be
able to produce quasi-coercive effects. In this way, process theism, while
maintaining that Gods agency in our universe is always persuasive, can
nevertheless account for the remarkable contingent order on which our
particular universe is based. This
suggestion, I should add, will not be found in Whiteheads writings. But it does seem consistent with his
position.
In sum: Although Whiteheadian process theology
shares with late modern thought the rejection of many of the senses in which
the universe had traditionally been thought to be designed, it can speak of our
universe as designed in two significant senses. In doing so, furthermore, it can arguably do justice to the best
scientific evidence about cosmic and biological evolution without being
undermined by the horrendous evils that have resulted from the creation of
life, especially human life.
Contributed by: David Ray Griffin
|