The Moral Status of Human Stem Cells
Human embryonic germ (EG) cells
are derived from the gonadal ridge tissue of an aborted fetus within five to
eight weeks after conception. The
procedure is analogous to the harvesting of organs from a cadaver. Here the
ethical issue is not so much the status of the aborted fetus, but whether those
who consider abortion an illicit act, despite its legality, can participate in
the research on tissues so derived.
The ethical status of human embryonic stem cells partly hinges on the
question of whether they should be characterized as embryos or specialized
bodily tissue. Although the answer to this question will be less important to
those who believe that the early embryo has little or no moral status, it will
shape the views of those who regard the embryo as significantly protectable.
One way of approaching this question is by looking first at ways in
which the embryo has been understood. In the context of the abortion and human
embryo research debates, a series of criteria has been proposed to determine
the moral status of the pre-implanation human embryo. Among these are an
entitys possession of a full human genome; its potential for development into
a human being; sentience; and the presence of well-developed cognitive
abilities such as consciousness, reasoning ability, or the possession of
self-concept. Those taking the position that the early embryo has full moral
status (equal to that of any child or adult human being) usually stress the
first two of these criteria: possession of a unique human genome and the potential for development into a
human being are regarded as sufficient for ascribing full moral status to it.
Since most cells in the human body possess a unique diploid genome and
are not regarded as morally protectable, the question of whether ES cells are
morally equivalent to somatic cells or whether they are more like human embryos
largely hinges on an understanding of stem cells potentiality. Here the matter
calls for further refinement since, as developments in mammalian cloning
technology suggest, any human cell (or tissue) may have the potential to become
a person. To avoid this problem, potentiality arguments typically appeal to
some consideration of normal or natural processes: embryos have a natural
potentiality to become a person in that the natural development of an embryo,
unlike tissue, is to become a human being. Of course, the interpretation and
significance of the word natural is controversial.
Can we conclude that stem cells have equivalent moral status because of
their potential to become a human being? Since potentiality is being understood
here as natural potentiality, determining the moral status of a stem cell
rests in part on whether its potential to become a person is natural, as it is
with embryos, or contrived, as it would be with cells that are cloned. Being
natural or contrived does not refer to the ease or facility of the process or
the need for technological intervention. Regardless of how cloning technology
may develop, for example, it will not be seen as a natural process by those who
hold that embryos have a natural potential to become a full human being. To
fail to distinguish between the natural and contrived development of the embryo
would otherwise, among other things, unreasonably commit us to the full moral
protection of every human cell.
The potential of a stem cell to become a human being seems to be much
more like that of a somatic cell that could be cloned than like an embryo. The
natural development of the individual cells of the embryonic disk (from which
stem cells are derived) is to become parts of a human being. Isolated from the
total structure of the embryo or blastocyst, these cells, even under favorable
growth conditions, will not develop the trophoblast (the outer layer of cells of the embryo) or other structures
needed for continued development. Another way of putting this is to say that
stem cells are pluripotent rather than totipotent. It is true that advanced
technology might be able to render these cells effectively (if not actually)
totipotent. Research undertaken in Canada in 1993 involving the aggregation of
mouse stem cells with a genetically manipulated embryo led to the cells subsequent
growth and population of the entire organism. However, such manipulations are arguably
even less natural than is current cloning technology. Insofar as potentiality
considerations alone are concerned, therefore, stem cells would not seem to
have the same moral status as embryos. For
those following this line of reasoning, including those who accord significant
moral status to the embryo, stem cells may thus be regarded and treated as any
other form of human bodily tissue.
Potentiality is a complex idea, drawing on even more complex and
undeveloped notions of nature and the natural. Rather than entirely
clarifying these matters, biology complicates them by indicating the
developmental continuum always present in human growth and maturation. Continuing
discussion will be needed involving the many viewpoints around the question
about how we can best protect the multiple values evoked by research at lifes
beginnings. These include values such as our commitment to the protection of
human life generally, the promotion of human health, and respect for the views
of others in a civil, democratic society.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback
| Contributed by: AAAS DoSER and the Institute for
Civil Society
|