McMullin, Ernan. Formalism and Ontology in Early Astronomy."
According to Ernan McMullin,
there are several crucial challenges to the relations between quantum mechanics
and theology. First, the discussion of both quantum mechanics and theology
often relies on a realist interpretation, but some of the most energetic
critics of realism are philosophers of quantum mechanics. Second, in dealing
with mechanics in general, and with quantum mechanics in particular, the move
from the mathematical formalism to its ontological interpretation is highly
problematic. The fact that quantum formalism yields two different ontologies
(those of Bohr and Bohm) leads to further problems: how can this be so, and how
is one to decide between them? Finally, one is faced with the troubling
strangeness of quantum ontology.
In this essay, McMullin
limits his concern to the history of the relation between formalism and
ontology in astronomy in order to show that similar difficulties arose
throughout this history. First he clarifies terms. Mathematical formalism tells
us nothing about the world until it is interpreted in terms of measurable
quantities, thus becoming a physical formalism such as quantum mechanics. Both
the Copenhagen interpretation and Bohms interpretation are then second level
interpretations between the physical formalism and ontology, and it is here
that issues arise which divide scientific realists and nonrealists.
With this in place, McMullin
turns to the early history of astronomy and finds similar difficulties in
moving from formalism to ontology. He starts with Greek astronomy, where the
celestial regularities invited explanation in terms of an underlying physical
structure. Aristotle, for example, regarded the mathematical formalism of
concentric spheres as implying a causal explanation based on the ontology of a
single interlocking system of spheres. But Apollonius and Hipparchus showed
that a complex, mathematical model based on the eccentric and the epicycle
could explain the data equally well, and this posed something similar to the
problem we find in quantum physics: how can two radically different ontologies
explain the same phenomena? Perhaps there is no genuine connection between
formalism and ontology; if there is, the criterion of saving the appearances
is clearly not enough in itself to reveal it.
McMullin next examines the
Copernican revolution from geocentrism to heliocentrism. Although both
formalisms could equally well save the appearances, Copernicuss system offered
important advantages. It eliminated unwanted elements of Ptolemys formalism
and it explained phenomena that were mere coincidences in the Ptolemaic system.
In addition, Copernicus could specify the order of the planets outwards from
the sun, their distances from the Earth, their periods of revolution, and their
retrograde motion. All of this disclosed such a degree of harmony that, for
Copernicus, it proved the reality of the earths motion and pointed to God as
its creator. McMullin closes this section by challenging Kuhns assessments of
the epistemic merits of Copernicuss system.
Kepler, we are next told,
strongly supported Copernicuss realist arguments for the motion of the earth,
both for religious reasons and because Copernicus offered such a convincing
explanation of the phenomena. His extensive analysis of Tycho Brahes
observations of Mars led Kepler to explain its orbit as elliptical and to
suggest a physics that could make such an orbit possible. Keplers theory of
gravity was analogous to magnetism and gave the Sun causal primacy in
determining planetary motion. But it was only with Newton that we at last have
a case sufficient to warrant reasonable belief in the heliocentric system. What
then of ontology? Certainly Newtons system employed terms like force and
attraction, but with his rejection of action-at-a-distance, the challenge of
finding an ontology to match the formalism remained. As McMullin points out,
this situation is obviously similar to the current problems in interpreting
quantum mechanics.
McMullin closes by drawing a
philosophical moral from this history of mechanical systems: moving from a
valid formalism to an underlying ontology has always been a contentious matter.
Mechanical agency has all along proved to be an uncommonly elusive quarry. On
the other hand, this history has forced us to expand our intuitive notions of
agency and, given the challenges raised by quantum mechanics, it seems clear
that further expansion is necessary. He also offers us a theological moral from
his historical account: if our explanation of motion at its most basic level is
more complicated and mysterious than earlier generations imagined, how much
more complex and mysterious must divine agency be, and how hesitant ought we to
be in discussing it.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback | Contributed by: CTNS/Vatican Observatory
|