Is the flagellum specified?
If the complexity of
the bacterial flagellum - where complexity is defined by Dembskis own unorthodox
criterion - has not been successfully demonstrated, then the matter of its specification could, perhaps, be set aside as no longer
relevant. Nonetheless, let us look at Dembskis development of
this portion of his argument for the specified complexity of the flagellum
In several places in No Free Lunch,
Dembski goes to considerable lengths to state the requirements that
specification and detachability must satisfy in the careful language of logic,
set theory and the like. The index of the book cites more than 40 pages dealing
with the topics of specification and detachability, plus approximately 100
page-citations for closely related topics such as specifiability,
specificational resources, biological specificity, and specified
complexity.
However, when it comes time for Dembski to
support his conviction that the bacterial flagellum is specified, the procedure
becomes considerably more casual, almost facile. Speaking on the specification
of biological systems in general, Dembski simply asserts that, Biological
specification always refers to function. An organism is a functional system
comprising many functional subsystems. In virtue of their function, these
systems embody patterns that are objectively given and can be identified
independently of the systems that embody them. Hence these systems are
specified in the sense required by the complexity-specification criterion.In these four brief sentences the foundation of Dembskis entire strategy for
certifying the specification of biotic systems is laid.
Addressing the particular question regarding
whether the bacterial flagellum is specified, Dembski confidently declares
that, Specification is never a problem. The irreducibly complex systems we
consider, particularly in biology, always satisfy independently given
functional requirements.... For instance, in the case of the bacterial flagellum,
humans developed outboard rotary motors well before they figured out that the
flagellum was such a machine.The flagellum functions like an outboard rotary motor. The rotary outboard
motor pattern represents a functional requirement independent of biological
systems. Therefore, concludes Dembski, the flagellum is specified.
This use of a human contrivance like the
outboard motor as the independent, detachable pattern that certifies the
flagellum as being specified bears further scrutiny. Following the quotation
above, Dembski continues: This is not to say that for the biological function
of a system to constitute a specification humans must have independently
invented a system that performs the same function. Nevertheless, independent
invention makes the detachability of a pattern from an event or object all the
more stark. At any rate, no biologist I know questions whether the functional
systems that arise in biology are specified.
Specified in the same technical sense
defined by Dembski? Specified by exhibiting an object/event-independent
pattern? Not necessarily. We need to look closely at the way in which Dembski
first introduced the concepts of specification and detachability. For a
pattern to count as a specification, the important thing is ... whether in a
certain well-defined sense it is independent of
the event it describes. Drawing a target around an arrow already embedded in a
wall is not independent of the arrows trajectory.Patterns that satisfy this condition of independence are designated as detachable. To determine if some particular pattern is
detachable, the following question must be answered affirmatively, says
Dembski: Given an event whose design is in question and a pattern describing
it, would we be able to explicitly identify or exhibit that pattern if we had
no knowledge of which event occurred?
To illustrate this test, Dembski uses the
event of coin-flipping and looks at numerical patterns that might be
generated by the sequence of heads and tails transcribed into strings of 0s
and 1s. If a string corresponding to the first 100 digits written in binary
form appeared, we would be warranted in believing that the sequence did indeed
conform to a detachable pattern. That numerical pattern
could easily be identified independently of the event
of coin flipping that generated it.
However, to move from Dembskis pattern
illustrations involving sequences of numbers or alphabetical letters (as in a
sentence of words) to biological systems requires, I believe, far more than a
hand-waving reference to biological functions playing the role of detachable
patterns. On what basis can Dembski assert, for instance, that Biological
specification always refers to function? Is this any different from drawing a
target (representing some particular biological function) around an arrow
already embedded in a wall (representing a functioning organism)? What is the
specific function of the flagellum that warrants being counted as a detachable specification
pattern? Its function as a means of locomotion? Apparently not. If that were
the case, would we not find ID books filled with claims that all animals
equipped with any means of locomotion were intelligently designed?
So, then, do only rotary
motor systems count as biological propulsion systems exhibiting a detachable
pattern in their function? On what basis would other propulsion systems be
disqualified? How narrowly does Dembski define biological function? And where
does he develop a system for determining that some functions count toward
specification and others do not? If it really is the case that, as Dembski
states, Biological specification always refers to function, wouldnt all biological functions then count as detachable patterns
exhibited by biological systems?
Apparently not. Although the E. coli cell is
a system rich with interacting structures and subsystems, each with an
important biological function, only the rotary propulsion function is cited as
being specified. On what basis is the function of the flagellum singled out as
the only bacterial function that is sufficiently spectacular to serve as
illustrative of a purported need for cinfigurational
assistance by an unidentified and unembodied
designer?
However, perhaps there is another approach
that deserves investigation. In our reflections on the question, Is the
flagellum complex? we argued that the focus of attention should be shifted from
the flagellum structure itself to the portion of the E. coli genome that coded
for its development. If that is correct, as it must be, then our search for a
detachable pattern should be directed toward the base pair sequence in E.
colis circular DNA molecule. Surely there is an identifiable pattern there
that characterizes the genetic coding for the flagellum, right? Right, indeed.
But the crucial question is, Is that pattern detachable
from the event under consideration, E. coli develops
a flagellum?
The answer to this question is a resounding,
No. The pattern in the base-pair sequence associated with this
flagellum-actualization event is unique to that event and to that event alone.
The pattern and the event are not independent, but stand in a one-to-one
relationship. This pattern is the epitome of non-detachability. The base pair
sequence pattern is like a blueprint for the flagellum. But the pattern itself
would never be recognized unless it were first provided the appropriate
environmental context and allowed to express itself in the formation of a flagellar appendage to a bacterial cell. The base-pair
sequence pattern in question is not detachable, and the flagellum is not
specified in the particular sense required by Dembskis
complexity-specification criterion.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback
| Contributed by: Dr. Howard Van
Till
|