Drees, Willem B. Evolutionary Naturalism and Religion."
According to Willem Drees,
at least three issues arise from an evolutionary view of nature. One is the
challenge to a literalist understanding of Genesis. Another is that evolution
may leave no room for divine action in the world. Finally, evolution can
radically modify our understanding of human nature and morality. The latter is
the focus of Drees paper. Rather than seeking an alternative to, or a
modification of, evolutionary ideas, Drees intends to stay as close as possible
to insights offered and concepts developed in the sciences. He call his
position naturalism and asks what the consequences are if a naturalist view
is correct. His central theses are: 1) upon a sufficiently subtle view of
science, evolution can do justice to the richness of experience and of
morality, but 2) not to the cognitive concerns of religion; nevertheless 3)
there is still room in a naturalist view for religion as a way of life and as a
response to limit questions concerning the scientific framework.
Drees first distinguishes
between soft or nonreductive naturalism, whose context is ordinary human
experience and language, and hard or reductive naturalism. The latter includes
epistemological naturalism (a universal application of the scientific method without
an ontological commitment) and ontological naturalism (Drees position). Within
ontological naturalism there are three varieties: reductive materialists, who
hold for type-type identity, nonreductive materialists, who opt for token-token
identity (Drees position), and eliminative materialists, who would reduce away
the higher level of discourse.
In Drees view, the natural
world is all that we know about and interact with; no supernatural realm shows
up within the world. All entities are made of the same constituents. Still
naturalism (or physicalism) can be non-reductive in the sense that higher level
properties may require their own concepts and explanatory schemes. Evolutionary
explanations are primarily functional. He argues that such a naturalism need
not be atheistic. Instead, physics and cosmology form the boundary of the
natural sciences and raise speculative, limit questions about the naturalist
view as such, questions about which naturalism can remain agnostic. The
integrity, coherence, and completeness of reality as described by science does
not imply its self-sufficiency. Contrary to Peter Atkins, Drees sees religious
accounts in which the natural world as a whole is dependent on a transcendent
Creator as consistent with, though not required by, naturalism. What Drees
rejects is a view of God as altering the laws of nature or as acting within the
contingencies of nature since, again, nature is complete and the integrity of
nature is affirmed.
Next Drees turns to
evolutionary explanations of morality. If morality, such as pro-social
behavior, is given an evolutionary explanation, can it still be considered
moral? Drees first argues that evolutionary naturalism as a whole should not
be dismissed because of the claims made by those whom Daniel Dennett calls
greedy reductionists. Instead Richard Alexander, David Sloan Wilson, Elliot
Sober, Michael Ruse and Francisco Ayala give serious consideration to the
importance of cultural and mental aspects in the evolutionary explanation of
morality. He describes four reasons why such accounts need not undercut the
validity of seeing morality as genuinely moral. For example, sociobiology
undermines the claim that values originate in a supernatural source, but people
are still free to choose from among competing values. Morality can go beyond
our emotions, as E. O. Wilson argues, and the contingencies of our evolutionary
history, as Michael Ruse proposes, to reflect a genuine distinction between is
and ought.
But what happens to religion
when it becomes the object of scientific study and explanation? Whereas
morality and experience seem to survive an evolutionary understanding, the
implications for religion are more serious. In effect, a functional and
immanent understanding of morality need not be as problematic to moral persons
as a similar understanding of religious language may be to believers, since
religious language typically refers to transcendent realities. Thus, some of
the fears by believers seem warranted. However, Drees holds that the grounds for
accepting a naturalistic evolutionary view of reality, including ourselves, are
strong. Hence, rather than backing away when a conflict threatens, he prefers
to reflect on the options for religion within an evolutionary framework.
According to Drees, naturalism
rules out objective reference to divine action in the world and it offers an
evolutionary account of how such ideas arose. Thus naturalism renders their
cognitive content extremely unlikely without claiming absolute proof.
Religious traditions can be studied as complex entities and ways of life, each
within its own environment. They embody regulative ideals and forms of worship,
and they undergird moral and spiritual commitments. Though their cognitive
claims may need revision, religions confront and challenges us with these
ideals and values, offering a vision for a better world. Moreover, they
encourage us to raise limit questions which naturalism alone cannot answer and
they in turn offer answers to such questions. The openness expressed in limit
questions can induce wonder and gratitude about the world, and this mystical
function of religion can be complementary to its more prophetic, functional
characteristics. Finally, evolution has bequeathed us the capacity for
imagination and thus for transcending any one particular perspective or
regulative ideal. This in turn leads us to the notion of divine transcendence.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback | Contributed by: CTNS/Vatican Observatory
|