Clayton, Philip. Tracing the Lines: Constraint and Freedom In the Movement from Quantum Physics to Theology."
Philip Clayton gives two
reasons why constructive theology should engage in dialogue with quantum
physics: it cannot afford the fideistic position that results from disengaging
with science, and it should seek a more hypothetical, fallible, and revisionist
method than traditionally allowed, thus opening itself up to the engagement
without becoming fully relativistic. Claytons method will be to consider an
array of interpretive models in a specific scientific field. He will then look
for areas of compatibility with theology, in the process revising both theology
and science. Eventually, he will repeat this activity across a variety of
disciplines. But why should physics provide constraints on how God might act?
Claytons response: it can do so if divine (or human) agency occurs in the
physical world in conformity with physical law. This obviously holds for us,
and it may indeed hold for the way God chooses to act. It thus becomes
Claytons wager: the structure of the physical world sets parameters on, and
tells us about the manner in which, God can act. He locates this position
midway between those who give a purely subjective account of theology or who
worry that quantum mechanics will not be helpful for divine action, and those
who seek even stronger theological conclusions from science or possibly the
convergence of science and religion.
Clayton then explores three
quantum mechanical constraints on divine action. The first is the role of the
observer. Minimalists focus on macroscopic measurements by an observer who is
never within the quantum mechanical system being studied. Maximalists introduce
subjectivity and consciousness in explaining a quantum experiment, despite the
resistance of many physicists. Here Clayton finds another crucial issue at
work: reductionism assumed by minimalists versus emergence and even dualism
assumed by maximalists. The second issue is the many-worlds interpretation as
represented by Hugh Everett, Bryce DeWitt, and others, compared with those who
defend the irreducible role of subjectivity in nature, such as Eugene Wigner,
John von Neumann, John Wheeler, Henry Stapp, and Roger Penrose. Both of these interpretations
are deeply influenced by metaphysics: physicalists who accept a branching
universe versus subjectivists who view quantum mechanics as evidence of mind as
irreducible in nature. Clayton then turns to his third issue, indeterminism and
free will. He reminds us how the early defenders of the Copenhagen view saw the
free choice of an experimenter as playing an irreducible role in the outcome of
the experiment. Despite counterarguments, Clayton claims that ontological
indeterminism remains a significant factor in these debates: it seems a
necessary condition for an incompatibilist view of free will, particularly if
incompatibilist free choices are to be enacted in the world. In turn one can
argue that God so created the world as to allow for human freedom.
Clayton then argues that
questions like these three show that physics and philosophy lie on a continuum,
particularly when the philosophical questions are closely connected with physics
research. Even theology lies on this continuum, though it is further removed
from physics research than from philosophy. Clayton now turns to three
additional issues. First he considers Bernard dEspagnats ontology, terming it
Spinozistic Monism. Here the state vector expresses properties of a deeper,
underlying reality which we can never describe in itself but which is
manifested in what we observe and which can be understood as Being. Next
Clayton engages critically those who interpret quantum physics in terms of
Eastern mysticism, including Capra, Bohm, and Wilber. Though their stress on
holism may be compelling, their metaphysical conclusions, like any others, are
options not directly supported by physics. Finally Clayton turns to theistic metaphysics,
considering both classical theism and panentheism. Theism asserts that the
world as it appears to us is real and that it has its origin in an ultimate
principle called spirit. The divine spirit is an active principle in this world
and is in many ways personal. Classical theism has advantages over the
preceding views, but it can become problematic if it places too great a
distance between God and the world; the analogy with human agency breaks down
for a fully disembodied view of God. To Clayton, panentheism avoids some of
these difficulties, particularly as it understands the world to be within God
even while, as with classical theism, God is more than and distinct from the
world. Here each physical event can be an expression of divine agency in a top-down
manner which does not violate physical law. It also provides a metaphysics that
coheres nicely with some of the interpretations of quantum physics previously
discussed, particularly those which stress holism, veiled reality,
interconnection, and interdependence.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback | Contributed by: CTNS/Vatican Observatory
|