Are We Alone?
The longest sustained Denkexperiment
devoted to trying to answer this third Cosmic Question - how to conceive of
other creatures in the universe who are not descended from our ancestors and
therefore do not belong to genus homo,
but who are rational and capable of movement, thought, and perhaps of free will
- was the thousand-year Medieval and Byzantine (as well as Jewish and Muslim)
investigation of angels. Though I should immediately add the caveat
that I am not considering the Jewish and Muslim developments here, as well as
the stipulation that several of us who work on the history of Medieval and
Byzantine thought have long posted a reward (or bounty) for anyone who could
find a scholastic dissertation about how many angels could dance on the head of
a pin! Both Athens and Jerusalem made
significant contributions to this investigation. Athens provided angelology with ontological categories and a
conceptual apparatus for locating angels within “the great chain of being”; as
Arthur O. Lovejoy put it in his celebrated William James Lectures of 1933 under
that title.
The accepted “philosophical,” as distinct from the dogmatic, argument
for the existence of angels rested upon these assumptions of the necessary
plenitude and continuity of the chain of beings; there are manifestly
possibilities of finite existence above the grade represented by man, and there
would consequently be links wanting in the chain if such beings did not
actually exist. The reality of the
heavenly hosts could thus be known a priori
by the natural reason, even if a supernatural revelation did not assure us of
it.
That assurance on the basis of what Lovejoy calls “supernatural
revelation” came not from Athens but from Jerusalem. To fill the categories provided by Athens, it was possible to
provide from Jerusalem a vast body of specific data: from the Cherubim who had been “placed at the east of the garden
of Eden, and a flaming sword which turned every way, to keep the way of the
tree of life” after the fall of Adam and Eve,to the prominent role of angels in the life of Christ, beginning with the
annunciation of Gabriel to Mary and the Christmas angels of Bethlehem and
closing with the angel who strengthened him during his prayer in the Garden of
Gethsemane and with “the angel of the Lord [who] descended from heaven, and
came and rolled back the stone from the door” of Christ’s sepulcher at the
resurrection, to
the starring role of the angels throughout the drama of the Apocalypse of John.
Perhaps nowhere does the joint contribution of Athens and Jerusalem to
this experiment in answering the third Cosmic Question “Are we alone?” become
more strikingly visible than in a pseudonymous sixth-century work carrying the
name of Dionysius the Areopagite, the shadowy figure mentioned in the Acts of
the Apostles as part of its account of Paul’s visit to Athens: The
Celestial Hierarchy, which, together with all the other writings of
Pseudo-Dionysius, has now finally become available in a careful and accurate
translation into English, with several introductions and with notes. At its very outset The Celestial Hierarchy quotes, from the
New Testament, the Epistle of James and the Epistle to the Romans,in order between these two proof texts to assert: “Inspired by the Father, each procession of the Light spreads
itself generously toward us, and, in its power to unify, it stirs us by lifting
us up. It returns us back to the
oneness and deifying simplicity of the Father who gathers us in.” That Neoplatonic doctrine of procession by
emanation from the Divine and of return to the Divine, buttressed by biblical
quotations, provides the foundation for positing the existence of the angels
and their “immaterial [nonmaterial] hierarchies” as the Neoplatonism of Athens
had taught, but also for explaining that the biblical writers of Jerusalem had
“clothed these immaterial hierarchies in numerous material figures and forms so
that, in a way appropriate to our nature, we might be uplifted from these most
venerable images to interpretations and assimilations which are simple and
inexpressible.” This was necessary
because, just as “the appearances of beauty are signs of an invisible
loveliness,” so “material means capable of guiding us as our nature requires”
were needed to let human minds, “in any immaterial way, rise up to imitate and
to contemplate the heavenly hierarchies.” Throughout the rest of this curious but
highly influential work, the concrete, empirical information of the biblical
narratives is called upon to supply such “figures and forms.”
On that basis, Thomas Aquinas, who, it has been estimated, quoted the Corpus Areopagiticum nearly a thousand
times in his writings,devoted an entire block of fifteen questions in Part I of the Summa Theologica, each question consisting
in turn of several articles, to a metaphysical-cum-exegetical
exposition of the doctrine of angels. Although Part I was the section of the Summa Theologica in which he examined what
was knowable by reason without revelation, Athens and Jerusalem were in
dialogue already in the first question of this treatise on angels:
Plato says in the Timaeus: “O gods of gods, whose maker and father am
I: You are indeed my works, dissoluble
by nature, yet indissoluble because I so will it.” But gods such as these can only be
understood to be the angels. Therefore
the angels are corruptible by their nature. . . .[To the contrary, according to
Thomas:] By the expression “gods” Plato
understands [not the angels, but] the heavenly bodies, which he supposed to be
made up of elements which are composite, and therefore dissoluble of their own
nature; yet they are for ever preserved in being by the Divine will.
Thus he drew upon Athens, the words of the Demiurge in Plato’s Timaeus, to explicate Jerusalem, biblical
teaching, but no less upon biblical teaching to explicate Greek
philosophy. And when Aquinas
subsequently took up “the local movement of angels,” the quotations were almost
all from Aristotle’s Physics; but
that should not be permitted to obscure the real source, in the usage of
Jerusalem, of such terms and concepts in this question as “a beatified angel”
or “the holy angels.” The clinching
argument of the first article on “the local movement of angels,” moreover, did
not come from Aristotle, nor from any other citizen of Athens, but from
Jerusalem. First he invoked the
fundamental distinction of Aristotle’s Physics
between potentiality and actuality, in order to set the stage for a biblical
proof text. In an argument that
fittingly illustrates the complex relationships in this “tale of two cities”
that I have been trying to tell, he linked these two sentences:
[The first, from
Athens:] The motion of that which is in
potency [potentiality] is on account of its own
need, but the motion of that which is in act [actuality] is not for
any need of its own, but for another’s need. [The second, from Jerusalem:] In this way, because of our need, the angel
is moved locally, according to Hebrews 1:14, “They are all ministering spirits,
sent to minister for them who receive the inheritance of salvation.”
Therefore it followed from this combination of authorities that in
order to carry out this ministry and mission to those “who receive the inheritance
of salvation,” as this had been documented throughout the Old and the New
Testament, it was necessary that the angels be capable of local movement. It had, after all, been by means of a
considerable amount of such “local movement” that “the angel of the Lord went
out, and smote in the camp of the Assyrians [commanded by Sennacherib] an
hundred fourscore and five thousand:
and when they arose in the morning, behold, they were all dead corpses.”
The effort of Thomas Aquinas, but also of Moses Maimonides, to
conceptualize the nature, the movement, and the knowledge of the angels was an
ambitious consideration of our third Cosmic Question, “Are we alone?” In this, as in the first two Cosmic
Questions, “Did the universe have a beginning?” and “Is the universe designed?”
it was the conjunction as well as the divergence between Athens and Jerusalem
that illumined the questions, provided material for the answers, and set the
terms for subsequent discussions of all three Cosmic Questions - including (Who
knows?) perhaps even the discussions that will follow later in this volume.
Contributed by: Dr. Jaroslav Pelikan
|