Meyering, Theo C. Mind Matters: Physicalism and the Autonomy of the Person."
Theo C. Meyering, in Mind
Matters: Physicalism and the Autonomy of the Person, takes yet a third
approach to the issue of reduction. He states that if (true, downward) mental
causation implies nonreducibility [as Stoeger and Murphy argue] and physicalism
implies the converse, it is hard to see how these two views could be
compatible. Meyering distinguishes three versions of reductionism: radical
(industrial strength) physicalism; ideal (regular strength) physicalism, and
mild or token physicalism. Radical physicalism asserts that all special
sciences are reducible to physics in the sense that their laws can be deduced
via bridge laws from those of physics. Ideal physicalism asserts that while it
is practically impossible to
reduce the special sciences, such reduction would be possible were there an
ideally complete physics" (Note: This distinction parallels Stoegers
recognition that epistemological reducibility is relative to the meaning of
laws of nature). Token physicalism is ontologically reductionist: there are no
events that are not token-identical with some
physical event or other (Note: See above, sec. 3.3). However, there are no
identities between higher-level and lower- level types of events; consequently some events described by the
special sciences have no physical explanation
at all.
All of these reductionist
positions are to be contrasted with compositional (milder than mild)
physicalism, which asserts that some higher-level events are not even
token-identical with physical events because the higher-level event (say, a
crash in the stock market) is constituted by innumerable physical particulars
in all sorts of states and interactions.
Meyering then surveys some
of the existing arguments for the nonreducibility of the special sciences. One
of the most important is the argument from multiple realizability. The claim is
that economics, for example, is not reducible to physics because economic
concepts (for example, monetary exchange)
are wildly multiply realizable (for example, using coins, strings of wampum,
signing a check). Thus, there can be no bridge laws and no reduction. Such an
argument, however, only cuts against radical physicalism, not the weaker (and a
priori more plausible) ideal physicalism.
A stronger argument for the
indispensability of special-science explanations is based on the role of
functional explanations. For example, the functional description of aspirin as
an analgesic is in some instances a more useful explanation of its causal role
(relieving a headache) than is its description as the chemical level.
Meyerings own contribution
focuses neither on multiple realizability of supervenient properties nor on
multiple fillers of functional roles, but on multiple supervenience. In
particular, a single subvenient
state of affairs (for example, a cloud of free electrons permeating the metal
of which a ladder is constructed) may realize a variety of supervenient dispositional properties (in this case,
electrical conductivity, thermal conductivity, opacity). An explanation (say,
of the cause of a deadly accident) requires reference to the dispositional
property (electrical conductivity), not merely to the subvenient property.
Meyering argues that it is this possibility of multiple supervenience, not
multiple realizability, that gives arguments against reduction based on
functional properties their real force. Downward causation, then, can be
understood in terms of selective activation of one of several dispositional
properties of a lower-level state, and thus can be assigned a stable place in
our picture of how the world is organized without upsetting our conception of
physics as constituting a closed and complete system of physical events.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback | Contributed by: CTNS/Vatican Observatory
|