Alston, W. Divine Action, Human Freedom, and the Laws of Nature.
In his paper Bill Alston
studies the philosophical aspects of the problem of divine action in relation
to both the laws of nature and the meaning of human freedom. To set the stage, he begins by stating two
presuppositions which characterize his general approach: first, he takes seriously and
realistically the idea of God as a personal agent, and second, Gods activity
extends beyond creation and conservation to include special acts performed by
God in light of knowledge of the world and to achieve a purpose.
By seriously Alston means
that, at least in some cases, we understand the statement God acts literally
and not just figuratively. By
realistically Alston means that religious discourse, along with scientific
discourse, aims at an accurate portrayal of an independently existing reality
with objective characteristics. Gods
actions result in outcomes, at least on some occasions, which are different from
the outcomes that would have been if only natural factors had been at
work. Gods acts include not only
revelation but also such super-spectacular miracles as the parting of the Sea
of Reeds and the resurrection, as well as daily divine-human interaction, in
prayer for example. Thus God acts as a
personal agent, possessed of intellect and will.
With this as background,
Alston proceeds to the main burden of the paper, relating his convictions to
the topics of natural law and human freedom.
He defines determinism as the doctrine that every happening is
uniquely determined to be just what it is by natural causes within the
universe. Although determinism has a
strong hold on contemporary culture, Alston takes quantum mechanics to provide
a definitive refutation of it. Hence
because of quantum indeterminism, God can act without violating physical
law. Moreover, acts such as these which
begin on the sub-atomic level can lead to differences in macroscopic
states. It is thus possible that God designed
the universe in this way to allow for divine action.
Still, Alstons main point
does not depend on the indeterminacy of quantum mechanics. According to Alston, even deterministic laws
only provide sufficient conditions for predicting the behavior of closed systems. But we never have
reason to believe a system is actually closed, i.e., that we know all the
operative forces at work. Any system
can be open to outside influences, including the acts of God. Hence, in this more general sense, Gods acts
do not violate natural law regardless of whether these laws are probabilistic
or deterministic.
Next Alston turns to the
problem of human freedom. He takes a
libertarian view of free action in which nothing other than my choice itself
uniquely determines me to choose
one way rather than another. Does
human freedom pose a problem for conceptualizing Gods action? Alston first argues that, with the exception
of acts by free creatures, all events which we attribute to Gods specific acts
could in fact be the unfolding of what God designed initially (whether
initially means temporally first, as in a universe with a first moment, or
first in order of priority, as in a universe with an infinite past). But if we assume that humans, at least, have
libertarian free choice, the strategy of initial design cannot work - unless God
can be said to possess middle knowledge, defined as knowledge of what (actual
and possible) free agents would choose to do in any situation in which they found themselves. Alston then argues that middle knowledge is
impossible: God cannot know what a free
agent would decide in situations which the agent never actually
encounters. Thus if there is libertarian
free agency and if middle knowledge is impossible, we must conclude that those
of Gods acts that appear to take place in time in response to the choices of
free agents do indeed take place in precisely that way, and not merely by means
of Gods initial design.
Alston then turns to
physical cosmology and its possible bearing on divine action. The choice between cosmological models such
as the Big Bang, the oscillating universe and inflation makes little difference
to Alstons position in general, though the status of time in these models
might be significant. To pursue this question,
Alston distinguishes between a block universe view of time and the process view
of time. Does human freedom require the
process view, or is the block view sufficient?
Alston argues that, although the latter denies the passage of time, it
does not imply that all events exist at all
times, but only that they each exist at their
own time. Thus the block
view does not undercut human
freedom, since all that is required for an act to be free is that it not be
determined by anything prior to it, and this is possible even on the block
view. Similarly God knows each event in
its own time.
Finally, what about Gods
existence: is it temporal or
atemporal? Alston argues that even if
God is atemporal, Gods acts can produce temporally ordered consequences in the
world. Moreover, relativity theory and
quantum cosmology suggest that time should not be viewed as a metaphysically
necessary form of every kind of existence, including the divine existence. Thus physical cosmology, and with it the
status of time, has little bearing on how we should best think of divine action
in the world and its relation to the laws of nature and human freedom.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback | Contributed by: CTNS/Vatican Observatory
|