The term the anthropic principle was coined by Brandon
Carter in 1974in bring together various large number coincidences about the universe which
had received scattered attention throughout this century. Although formulated
in a variety of ways,
in its strongest form the AP poses the following question: How are we to
explain the fact that the values of the fundamental constants of nature (e.g.,
the speed of light, Plancks constant, etc.) and the form of the fundamental
physical laws are precisely what is needed if the evolution of life is to
possible? Estimates have been made which suggest that if the values of the
natural constants differed from their actual values by one part per million, it
would have been impossible for life to have evolved in the universe.
To some, then, the universe seems fine-tuned for life,
suggesting a cosmological version of the design argument for God.Opponents have deployed a variety of many worlds arguments. Perhaps there are
many universes, existing as distinct domains of one actual universe or as other
actual universes disconnected from our own, each with different values of the
natural constants, perhaps even different physical laws.It is then a tautology that we evolved in that particular universe whose
conditions are the prerequisites for life.
The following represent positions on the AP.:
i) On design arguments: John Barrow and Frank
Tipler published a massive study of the AP as a design argument, including its
historical background and philosophical development, its relation to
astrophysics, quantum mechanics and biochemistry. They also offer speculative
implications for life in the universe, particularly in the far future,which Tipler later discusses in detail (see Part 2, E, 3 below). John Leslie
has collected and analyzed numerous forms of the argument. His overall
evaluation is that, while the multiple worlds hypothesis seems to me
impressively strong, the God hypothesis is a viable alternative to
it...Contemporary religious thinkers (often assume that ) design arguments can
have absolutely no force. I hope to have shown that philosophy has demonstrated
no such thing.Leslie then adopts a Neoplatonic view of God as an aesthetic/ethical principle.
Ernan McMullin, however, after pointing out the connection between
fourteenth-century debates on contingency and the AP, stresses the problems in
claiming that the AP is an explanation even in the context of Christian presuppositions,
the basically teleological character of the AP mode of reasoning, and its
vulnerability to theory-change in science.
After a careful reading of contending arguments, Mark
Worthing cautions that, given the cosmological evidence, the designer of the
universe need not be the Creator of God of theism: both a divine demiurge,
including the universe per se (as Dawkins suggests), or an emerging divinity,
as the Barrow/Tipler model requires, takes into account the empirical evidence
of design. In essence, unaided reason is a limited approach to God.According to Barbour, the theological implications of the AP as a modern design
argument are minimal: ...even if the arguments are accepted, they would not
lead to the personal, active God of the Bible... but only to an intelligent
designer remote from the world... Natural theology can show that the existence
of God is a plausible hypothesis, but (this is) far removed from the actual
life of a religious community.
ii) On many worlds: Though not supporting design
per se, Bill Stoeger has argued against the kind of empirically unwarranted
mathematical extrapolations used to support the many worlds position.
Admittedly the mathematical structure of theoretical physics and cosmology can
be seen as describing not just our universe but an ensemble of universes.
Still, unless one is a Platonist, the fact that such an extrapolation is
possible mathematically does not entail that these universes necessarily exist.
The crux of Stoegers argument is that the efficacy of nature lies in nature
and not in the laws we say it obeys (i.e., science is descriptive, not
prescriptive). Ultimately the existence of the universe is unanswerable by
science.
iii) On the AP in theology: As early as 1979 Peacocke
gave the AP an indirect but important role within his discussion of the
doctrine of creation, using the metaphors of God as elaborating a fugue and as
a bell-ringer sounding the changes.George Ellis has
explored what he calls the Christian Anthropic Principle, combining design
perspectives with a theology of divine omnipotence and transcendence and
drawing from William Temple. Fine-tuning leads not to evidence for God; instead
it is seen as a consequence of what we mean by God as the Creator of life whose
goal is the eliciting of a free response of love and sacrifice from free
individuals. This approach then leads to five implications, including the
orderliness of the universe that allows for free will, Gods self-limitation in
giving up intervention, the possibility of revelation, the existence of pain
and evil and Gods hiddenness in the world as entailed by the impartiality of
the laws of nature. Nancey Murphy,however, treats Ellis thesis as an argument for God. She reconstructs Ellis paper
using a Lakatosian structure in order to show that theology can be seen as a
science and that cosmological fine-tuning can serve as an auxiliary hypothesis
in such a theological program. The Lakatosian novel fact in the Temple-Ellis
approach is that God designed the universe to be both law-governed and
fine-tuned; the former, being irrelevant to Temple, is thus weakly novel.In further writings, Ellis argues that science is not designed to deal with
ultimate causation. Instead we need take into account both scientific and
broader views. A similar approach was taken by Murphy and Ellis in further
work involving ethics and kenotic theology (see Section 2,E,2 below).
Richard Swinburne has drawn on the AP to augment his ongoing
program to defend the case for theism.He concludes, I believe (the evidence here and elsewhere) render the existence
of God significantly more probably than not.According to John Polkinghorne, the AP raises a profound opening for natural
theology by pointing to the finely tuned balance in the laws of nature,
enabling the evolving history of the universe to achieve its astonishing
fruitfulness... It also offers a promising area of interaction with other
world religions.
In my view, the AP does not serve primarily as a basis for
an argument for God. In fact, one can see elements of both contingency and
necessity arising dialectically in both sides of the design / many worlds
debate and leading to differing levels of abstraction and suggestions of
further design and many worlds.The AP can, however, play a fruitful role if incorporated within ongoing
constructive theology, illuminating its inner meaning and suggesting
connections between theological topics we might not otherwise have recognized.
For example, it helps make explicit the subtle implications of Pannenbergs
famous dictum, the universe as a whole and in all its parts is contingent.
The AP also underscores the key role that Plancks constant plays in the
particular overall structure of the universe, a role that a theology of
creation ex nihilo would need to take seriously. The same constant may
be a critical factor in compatibilist discussions of free will and thus for
theological anthropology: for us to act, nature at the physical level must,
arguably, be indeterministic.It also functions pivotally in some approaches to non-interventionist divine
action, particularly in the context of theistic evolution (see Part 2, C, 2
below).
Contributed by: Dr. Robert Russell
|