Wildman, Wesley J. Evaluating the Teleological Argument for Divine Action."
But can we make a connection between the appearance of purposes or ends
in nature and the reality of divine action by arguing that such ends indicate
genuine teleology and that such teleology is a mode of Gods action? Wesley
Wildman calls this position the teleological argument for divine action and
provides an extensive analysis of its problematic status. Its more aggressive
form as a design argument, as given by William Paley and Alfred Russel Wallace,
has been undermined by evolutionary biology, but more modest forms are still
possible. Wildman claims that no detailed, supportive argument from biology to
theories of divine action can be given, nor can evolution destroy such
theories, but biology can influence them to some degree. The principle reason
is the metaphysical ambiguity which effects each of three major steps in the
argument, though it is generally left unnoticed.
Before proceeding, Wildman distinguishes between apparent and real
ends, and between open-ended and closed-ended processes. In addition, given the
dubious aspects of Aristotles use of final causes and the equally unnecessary
abandonment of teleology in contemporary causal explanation, he includes a
four-fold schema regarding teleology. 1) Against Dawkins, who argues that ends
are only apparent, Wildman cites Monods views about teleonomy and chaos. 2) Given
that complex systems are open-ended, he asks whether one specific end can be
achieved, and by an intentional agent? 3) Moreover, are high-level
characteristics of living systems due to the complex external arrangement of
their parts, or to the emergence of genuine internal relations? 4) Is teleology
expressed in the laws of nature, in chance, or in some basic constituent of
nature like mind?
Now Wildman turns to the first stage in the argument. Given that the
appearance of ends in nature is ubiquitous, can we establish that real purposes
give rise to them? And preliminary to this, are apparent ends in nature only
merely apparent? According to Wildman, modern biology has produced the
strongest possible reason for answering these affirmatively with its use of
efficient causal explanations of apparent ends. Still the conclusion depends on
two points which Wildman carefully criticizes: a principle of metaphysical
minimalism and a claim that all ends in nature, outside those achieved by
agents, can exhaustively be explained solely by means of efficient causes. His
position includes scientific and philosophical arguments about the sufficiency
of efficient causal explanations.
The second stage requires a metaphysical bridge between real ends in
nature, as in the preceding stage, and broad teleological principles which can
be connected with a theory of divine action. The problem here is that some
teleologies are not amendable to such theories. Foremost is Aristotles
metaphysics, with its unmoved prime mover. Others include the Chinese concept
of li, the Buddhist view of a
purposive nature without God, and theistic mystical theology.
In the third stage Wildman traces the links between metaphysical
contextualizations of teleology and theories of divine action, stressing the
metaphysical ambiguity which complicates these links. If the locus of the
teleological principle is natural law, divine action can only involve the
universal determination of natural possibilities and the ontological grounding
of nature. If the locus includes chance, divine action can be expressed more
directly. If it also includes the constituents of nature, God may offer the
initial aims to actual occasions, or the material conditions for the emergence
of self-organizing systems.
According to Wildman, then, the teleological argument for divine action
is not easily established. There is no unbroken chain of implications from
apparent ends in nature to real ends to fundamental teleological principles to
the modes of divine action. Additional premises are needed to connect the
chain, and none of these is furnished by biological evolution. Moreover, there
are profound teleological visions that are antagonistic toward divine action
and are equally well supported by evolution. The failure of the teleological
argument is located in its underlying metaphysical ambiguity. On the other
hand, apparent purposes in nature are not incompatible with teleological
theories of divine action; indeed, the implications run more smoothly in this
direction. In closing, Wildman offers a final conjecture: if ones premise is
that the universe is meaningful, then one is led to affirm that the universe
has an overarching teleological sweep. Alternatively, those popular writers on
biology who avoid postulating a fundamental teleological principle must either
assume that the cosmos is absurd or refuse to consider the implications of
their premise.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback | Contributed by: CTNS/Vatican Observatory
|