Cela-Conde, Camilo J. and Gisele Marty. Beyond Biological Evolution: Mind, Morals, and Culture.
Camilo Cela-Conde and Gisele
Marty focus on models of human evolution that account for the development of
traits in individuals, including morphological traits such as large brains and
functional traits such as speech. They also consider the development of
collective traits in human populations, such as language, culture, and moral
codes. These models raise important theological questions regarding divine
action.
Most theological attempts to
address human evolution treat the development of culture separately from, or in
contrast to, the evolution of morphology, but these attempts run into serious
problems since cultural evolution presupposes and builds on biological
evolution. Interactionist models are thus needed. Such models must also address
the question of when and how such traits as a complex brain and human language
emerged during the past 2.5 million years. Some scientists hold for an almost
instantaneous and isolated emergence of language, but since language does not
fossilize, the conjecture is hard to test empirically. Others argue for a long,
gradual, and early development of language going back to Homo habilis, and relate it to the slow
development of the brain, an idea which is easier to test. Another question is
how to differentiate the evolution of our species from other hominids and even
from other primates. The theological task, in turn, is how to relate such an
understanding of human evolution, especially of language and cognition, to
divine action, taking into account the elements of continuity as well as
discontinuity between humans and other hominids as well as between hominids in
general and other primates.
Darwin was the first to
speak of both a biological mechanism for moral behavior and a distinctive
moral sense which he attributed uniquely to humans. He explained the evident
diversity of moral codes in terms of adaptation to varying environments. But
how does human moral sense (or moral altruism) differ from the kind of
biological altruism shared by so many species, and what are its genetic roots?
This question leads the authors into a discussion of sociobiology as it has
developed over the past two decades. In their view, it has focused on four key
issues: the phenomena implied by human morality; the analogs to it at the
animal level; the phylogenetic explanation of the emergence of these analogs;
and the development of human morality within this framework. Though the debate
has waned somewhat, Cela-Conde and Marty hope to show how it might now be
reinvigorated.
Part of the challenge, in
spite of the reductionism inherent in the debate, is the actual complexity of
the phenomenon of human morality. A variety of approaches are being pursued.
Some scientists point to the distinction between the capacity for, and the
content of, moral thought. Others focus on group selection and kin selection
models of altruism. Some argue for a strict separation between biological and
moral altruism, while others stress their intimate connection. The authors note
that, even if a strong connection is granted, reductionism can at least be
partially avoided by appealing to the supervenience of moral language. Some sociobiologists
have developed theories of reciprocal altruism, ultrasociality, and
sociocultural fitness. Still the authors know of no model which includes all
the elements required, from innate tendencies to empirical moral norms.
Moreover, the complex cognitive processes implied in evaluating and making
decisions suggest that the usual distinction between motive and criterion is
inadequate.
Instead, in their model,
Cela-Conde and Marty consider both the motive to act, the personal ethical
criterion, and the set of collective values and norms. Individuals accumulate
and actualize these values during the apprenticeship process, giving to the
collective complex an evolutionary, changing character. They propose a
phylogenetic argument that places biological and moral altruism as two
successive stages in human evolution. Biological altruism is closely associated
with the genetic code and belongs to the area of motivation; moral altruism is
related to the personal ethical domain or the values of the group. Neither taken
alone is able to explain the whole of human moral conduct. The combined
development of cognitive capacity and moral behavior is sometimes called
co-evolution. They also draw on the cognitive sciences. Here, internal
rewards to the individual may be available through religious rituals, acting
before public crowds, integration into small communities, and so on. They
conclude by exploring the idea of universal norms directing moral behavior as
typified in the first stages of sociobiology, and the idea of universal
tendencies to accept moral codes as found in later, more sophisticated
sociological arguments. These results and their problems point, in turn, to the
need for a more complete theory linking the biological substratum to moral
conduct, the influence of social groups, and the role of emotions in
maintaining moral behavior.
Email
link | Printer-friendly | Feedback | Contributed by: CTNS/Vatican Observatory
|