B. Critical Realism: The Original Bridge Between Science and Religion.
In his ground-breaking 1966 publication, Issues in
Science and Religion, Ian G. Barbour laid out a series of well-crafted
arguments involving issues in epistemology (the kinds of knowledge we have),
language (how it is expressesd), and methodology (how it is obtained and
justified). Together
these arguments provided the bridgebetween science and religion which has, more than any other work, made possible
the developments of the past four decades. He has
explored these arguments in detail since then, principally through his 1990
Gifford Lectures, together with their revisions in 1997and 2000. Barbours
pioneering vision continues to bear much of the now burgeoning flow of traffic.
From the outset, Barbour used the term critical realismto stand for the specific set of arguments he developed in 1966, as have many
other scholars since then.
Barbour viewed critical realism as an alternative to three
competing interpretations of scientific theories: (1) classical or naive
realism: scientific theories provide a photographic representation of the
world; (2) instrumentalism: scientific theories are mere calculative devices,
and (3) idealism: scientific theories depict reality as mental. Instead, from a
critical realist perspective, scientific theories yield partial, reviasable,
abstract, but referential knowledge of the world. Scientific theories are
expressed linguistically through metaphors and models. Drawing on Max Black,
Mary Hesse, Donald Schon, and others, Barbour defined metaphor as an open-ended
analogy whose meaning cannot be reduced a set of literal statements.Scientific models, in turn, are systematically developed metaphors. (M)odels
and theories ... selectively represent particular aspects of the world for
specific purposes... (They) are to be taken seriously but not literally.
Barbour then turned to the current discussion of scientific
methodology, with major breakthroughs by such philosophers of science as N. R.
Hanson, Gerald Holton, Thomas Kuhn, Michael Polanyi, Steven Toulmin, and with
special emphasis on the writings of Imre Lakatos.He began with the empiricism of Carl Hempel, whose hypothetico-deductive
method brought together inductivist and deductivist approaches to the
construction and testing of theories vis. Popperian falsificationism.In the 1960s, this method was fundamentally recast. It was now seen to operate
within both the historicist and contextualist elements which characterize the
scientific community. These elements include the theory-laddenness of data, the
presence of intersubjectivity rather than strict objectivity in scientific
rationality, the structure of science through paradigms and their revolutions
in the history of science, the presence of metaphysical assumptions about
nature in scientific paradigms, and the role of aesthetics and values in theory
choice. Scientific theories are a human construction and their conclusions are
inherently tentative and subject to revision. Nevertheless, according to
Barbour, they are to be assessed by four criteria which are reasonably
trans-paradigmatic: agreement with data, coherence, scope and fertility.
Barbour used these criteria to articulate what he called a
critical realist theory of truth.
Like classical realism, the meaning of truth in critical realism is
correspondence with reality (i.e., reference) and the key criterion of truth is
agreement of theory with data. But we often have only indirect evidence for our
theories; moreover, networks of theories are tested together. Thus internal
coherence and scope also serve as criteria of truth, as stressed by
rationalists and philosophical idealists. Even this is insufficient when
competing theories are equally coherent and comprehensive; hence fruitfulness
serves as a fourth criterion of truth, as pragmatists, instrumentalists and
linguistic analysts stress. Thus intelligibility and explanatory power, and not
just observableness or predictive success, is a guide to the real.
Turning to philosophy of religion, Barbour constructed a
similar defense of critical realism. Here his sources in religious
epistemology, methodology and language include the writings of John Wisdom,
John Hick, Ian Ramsey and Frederick Ferré.With these arguments in place, Barbour was prepared to make his crucial,
bridging methodological claim: the basic structure of religion is similar to
that of science in some respects, though it differs at several crucial points.Similarities: Both science and religion make cognitive claims about the
world using a hypothetico-deductive method and a contextualist and historicist
framework. Both communities organize observation and experience through models
seen as analogical, extensible, coherent and symbolic, and these models are
expressed through metaphors.Differences. But there are important differences in the data of
religion compared to that of science.Religious models serve non-cognitive functions which are missing in science,
such as eliciting attitudes, personal involvement and transformation. Moreover,
compared to science, where theories tend to dominate models, in religion models
are more influential than theories.Religion lacks lower-level laws such as those found in science, and the
emergence of consensus seems an unrealizable goal. Religion also includes
elements not found in science such as story, ritual, and revelation through
historical events.
Barbours argument culminates in his use of paradigm
analysis to place science and religion on a continuous spectrum in which both
display subjective as well as objective features, though the former are
more prominent in religion and the latter in science.The subjective features include the influence of theory on data, the
resistance of comprehensive theories to falsification, and the absence of rules
for choice among paradigms.Objective features include the presence of common data on which disputants can
agree, the cumulative effect of evidence for or against a theory, and the
existence of criteria which are not paradigm-dependent. It is the dynamic
tension between similarities and differences, and between subjective and
objective features in both science and religion, that together make Barbours
analysis so original and fruitful.
Yet even while Barbour was developing this position,
scientific realism was being challenged in a number of ways.Though Kuhn had focused primarily on factors internal to the scientific
community, sociologists from the 1970s on explored the social construction of
science. These externalist accounts of science emphasized the social
history of science and the variety of political and economic influences on
science. According to one school (the strong program), the theory-ladenness
of data and the underdetermination of theories by evidence heavily influence
the formation and content of scientific theories and the ways they are
assessed. At the same
time, Marxists argued that science is a source of power over nature and thus
over people, power rationalized by appeals to the myth of objectivity.
Meanwhile the diversity of philosophical views on realism in science was
growing, along with an increasing number of anti-realist positions.
Realists frequently argued that social and personal influences are gradually
filtered out by the methods of testing used in the sciences. Moreover, the
increasing success in predictive power and technological application implies
that scientific knowledge is referential.Barbours recent assessment is that these externalist accounts provide a
valuable corrective to the internalist view, particularly regarding the
context of discovery. However, the appeal to interests is hard to document and
it underestimates the constraints on theories by data and the fact that the
testing of theories reduces distortions due to ideologies and interests.
Finally, the charge of cultural relativism should apply to the externalist
claim as well.
Barbours arguments have been developed in significant and
diverse ways by a variety of scholars. In his 1979 Bampton Lecturesand in his 1983 Mendenhall Lectures,Arthur Peacocke endorsed critical realism in both science and religion.
In science, where challenges to realism from sociologists of knowledge were
mounting, Peacocke draw on arguments for realism by Ernan McMullin, Hilary
Putnam and Ian Hacking.In his 1993 Gifford Lectures,
Peacocke acknowledged the diversity of positions held by scientific realistsbut argued for a common core of claims: that scientific change is progressive
and that the aim of science is to depict reality. Peacocke made a similar case
for critical realism in theology, where the social conditioning of beliefs is
generally assumed. As in science, theological concepts and models are partial,
inadequate, and revisable, and, unlike those in science, they include a strong,
affective function. Still Peacocke views them as (the) necessary and, indeed,
the only ways of referring to God and to Gods relation with humanity,
though he stresses that referring to God (e.g., the via positiva) does
not mean describing God (the via negativa).Its grounding in a continuous community and interpretive tradition make it
reasonable to accept theologys explication of religious experience, though
metaphorical and revisable, as an inference to the best explanation.
Other scholars in theology and science have taken similar
approaches. According to John Polkinghorne, critical realism is the best
explanation of the success of science, the only philosophy adequate to
scientific experience, and the view most congenial to scientists themselves. In
his 1994 Gifford Lectures, Polkinghorne drew on Thomas Torrance and Polanyi in
highlight the doubly circular character of knowledge: belief and understanding
are mutually entailing, and what is known and the knowledge of it are mutually
conforming. Scientific
theories are shaped by the way things are, offering an ever increasing degree
of verisimilitude as suggested by his motto, epistemology models ontology.Polkinghorne offers similar arguments for theology, too. (F)rom a theological
perspective, all forms of realism are divinely underwritten, for God will not
mislead us.... Wentzel van
Huyssteen, in his earlier writings, also viewed theology from a realist
perspective, claiming that theology ... is scientifically committed to a
realist point of view and describing the referential power of theological
language about God as reality depiction. For van Huyssteen, the hypothetical
status of scientific statements become the eschatological dimension of
theological statements.Thomas F. Torrance, too, argues for the scientific character of theology
because, like the natural sciences, it adopts a method which is determined by
its object. For theology, the object is God, known to us by Gods revelation in
the incarnation and resurrection of the Word. Thus the theoretical structures
of theology disclose knowledge of God just as the theoretical structures in
science, like Einsteins general relativity, provide objective knowledge of
this world. According
to Torrance, natural theology can find a place within positive theology, though
not as a prolegomenon to it --- a view which he reports he persuaded Karl Barth
eventually to accept.
The central role Barbour gave to metaphors, models and
paradigms in both science and theology has stimulated wide discussion, too. In
1982, Sallie McFague drew directly from Barbours workin pointing to basic similarities between models in theology and in science,
but she also stressed four important differences: they provide order in
theology while stimulating new discoveries in science; they more clearly carry
meaning in theology than in science; and unlike in science, they are ubiquitous
and hierarchical, as well as eliciting feelings and action, in theology.McFague combined this with Paul Ricoeurs notion of metaphor as is and is not
in developing what she then termed metaphorical theology. Using this approach
she has developed new metaphors for God as Mother, Lover, and Friend, and the
world as the body of God which challenge theologys patriarchical and
androcentric distortions and fund her work in ecological theology. In 1984,
Mary Gerhart and Allan Russellcontrasted two meanings of analogy: 1) as an extension of our conceptual
network from a known to an unknown and 2) as a new and dynamic relation between
two separate networks which distorts both and induces tension. They call the
latter metaphor, concluding that the relation between science and religion is
itself a metaphor.In 1985 Janet Soskicepublished a thorough study of metaphor in religious and scientific language,
emphasizing the distinction between metaphor and model which she found
conflated in Black, Barbour, Ferré and David Tracy.Although she vigorously defended theological realism, Soskice also stressed the
social and contextual nature of scientific realism, in which theoretical terms
are seen as representing reality without claiming to be representationally
privileged. Theological realism, in turn, distinguishes between referring to
God and defining God, and employs a causal theory of reference.In 1988, Hans Küng applied paradigm analysis to the history of theology and
compared the results to the history of science.In contrast to the way paradigms are successively replaced in science, giving
it an irreversible history, in theology contrasting paradigms, such as Thomism,
Reformation theology, modernity, may well coexist in history. In science the
next revolution comes at the limits of the existing paradigm. In theology the
primal testimony of scripture and the events of the history of Israel and
Jesus Christ are the sources of each new revolution.
An important development has been the theme of consonance
introduced in 1981 by Ernan McMullin. His concern was the search for a
coherence of world-view to which all forms of human knowing can contribute.
The consonance that characterizes such a world-view does not require or even
expect direct support.Instead it would involve mutual contributions in a relation that is tentative
and open to constant slight shift. Beginning in 1989, I combined McMullins
idea with McFagues epistemic claim about the is and is not structure of
metaphor to include and thus to learn from both consonance and dissonance
between scientific and theological theories. Rather than undercutting a
coherent world-view, dissonance points to the dynamic character of our world
view, specifying where problems arise, shifts are required, and potentially
greater coherence can be sought. Moreover, by recognizing that theories in both
science and theology evolve and are eventually replaced, we can build change
directly into the relation between science and theology rather than being
threatened by it.
Over the past decade, Ted Peters has developed this approach
in terms of what he calls hypothetical consonance.If consonance in the strong sense means complete harmony or accord, we might
hope to find (it), but we have not found it yet. What we do have are shared
domains of inquiry or consonance in a weak sense, but this is enough to
encourage further exploration. He bases this on his critical realist assumption
that theologians and scientists are seeking to understand the same reality.The qualifier hypothetical reminds theologians to treat their assertions as
fallible and subject to possible disconfirmation as well as confirmation. Willem
B. Drees, though exploring the concept of consonance, has pointed out the
problemmatic assumptions underlying realism and a correspondence theory of
truth. Instead he proposes constructing a consonance world which includes
Gods otherness and the prophetic challenge of lived values.Our religious traditions invite us to wander through, and our sciences to
wonder about, the reality which transcends and sustains our lives and to engage
ethically with the challenge of the future.
Contributed by: Dr. Robert Russell
|